Saturday 2 May 2015

Resisting Prejudice or the Non-People who Ruin Communities?

This paper was accepted at the North East Modern Languages Association Convention (May 2015).



In May 2014, Toronto city councillor and recent mayoral candidate Doug Ford attended a resident’s meeting to discuss the emergence of The Griffin Centre, a home for autistic children in Toronto.  Many of the residents were angry that the home opened, and according to news reports, were quoted as saying, “This is not a place for mental people. This is a residential area” and “This is a community for people, not for that.” Doug Ford, further, added to the turmoil by telling Griffin Centre staff that they had “ruined the community.” (Shephard, 2014).
Utilizing Rosemarie Garland-Thomson’s (1997) assertion that a poststructuralist apprehension of “the complexity of social power relations can readily transfer to analysis of disability” (p.20) and specifically the importance of Michel Foucault’s biopolitical considerations of “the population as a political problem” (Foucault, 1976, p.245) this paper will address the recent disqualification of so-called non-people by Toronto community members (and councillors alike) to question how human value is articulated, both in public forums and the media.
Specifically, this paper will demonstrate that “discourse transmits and produces power” for it to seem acceptable for city residents and councillors to publicly discriminate against mentally challenged children but also the local media’s outraged reaction to this event also “exposes it, renders it fragile and makes it possible to thwart it” (Foucault, 1978, p.101). In conclusion, this paper will argue this recent highly publicized event provides a larger paradigmatic model to apprehend ability and disability and conceive of who count as people or what counts as human in contemporary Toronto.

Colin Barnes’s (1992) work on the cultural and philosophical foundations of disability discrimination argues that Social Darwinism has an “understandable appeal to a society dominated by a relatively small elite of property-owning, ‘rational’ individuals” (Barnes, 1992). If concepts of natural selection can be applied to human societies and the social domain, at least in the perpetuation of favourable human traits, it seems that “a relatively small elite of property-owning, ‘rational’ individuals” in Etobicoke (a former Toronto municipality) vehemently expressed the desire deselect developmentally disabled children from their community in order to sustain an imagined sense of residential order and, moreover, categorize autistic teenagers as socially invalid. Irrespective of Doug Ford’s mediated involvement in the fracas (as a councillor seeking municipal election) and his subsequent comment about a community being ruined (stated as an opportunistic attempt to appeal to potential voters) Etobicoke community members clearly discriminated between two types of people, the us and the them, the acceptable and the unacceptable or more specifically people and non-people.
Michel Foucault argues that individualizing categories of people acts to maintain power relations and, moreover, Foucault (1977) also states,  “the child is more individualized than the adult, the patient more than the healthy man, the madman and the delinquent more than the normal and the non-delinquent,” (p.193). Therefore, developmentally disabled potentially delinquent children in professional care have the capacity to be more individualized than others. Furthermore, leading Disability Studies scholar Rosemarie Garland Thomson (1997) claims “the complexity of social power relations can readily transfer to analysis of disability” (p.20) in the sense that Foucault (1977) establishes that “discipline makes individuals” (p.170) and the power of normalization (as a disciplinary technique) individualizes by measuring the differences between those deemed to be so-called normal and abnormal and subsequently qualifying “membership in the homogenous social body,” (p.184) which the Etobicoke community, in particular, demonstrated by disqualifying individuals with disabilities from their homogenous social body and categorizing them as abnormal, “mental” or even “non-persons” (Shephard, 2014).  Consequently, if power holds over the life of living beings and biopolitics deals with the problematic elements in a human population, not only through disciplinary techniques of individualizing but also regularizing populations accordingly, (Foucault, 1976) these two techniques of biopolitical power, discipline and regulation, both function through the application of norms because, “the norm is something that can be applied to the body one wishes to discipline and a population one wishes to regularize” (Foucault, 1976, p.253). Therefore, the vocal pronouncement (or application) of desired norms (“this is a community for people”) and undesired abnormalities (“this is not a place for mental people”) at an Etobicoke meeting, then, functions to discipline developmentally disabled individuals (by individualizing them as “mental” and dividing them from the so-called “non-mental” community members) and also thereafter regularize a local Toronto community population. The following desire to regularize an Etobicoke community according to its resident’s wishes, then, provides the basis for an application of preferred location specific norms, which provide the basis for, what linguistics scholar Ruth Wodak (2004) calls, an “us and them discursive strategy “or the “the positive self and the negative other presentation” (p.207) that make it seem acceptable (at least to those in the meeting) to discriminate against (or discipline) autistic children.       
            However, if a thorough analysis of individualizing the developmental disabled and their subsequent subjugation (in Etobicoke) is provided by a Foucauldian apprehension of the complexity of power relations it is first important to conceive, as Foucault (1978) articulates, that “power is not an institution nor a structure,” whether it is the institution of Etobicoke residents or the structure of the city municipality but instead “a complex strategical situation in a particular society,” (p.93) which in this case is the discursive strategy of transmitting, sustaining and justifying specific power relations by publicly declaring specific individuals (with disabilities) as having less value than others (who do not).
For statements like “This is not a place for mental people. This is a residential area” and “This is a community for people, not for that.” (Shephard, 2014) to be articulated in a public space in order to potentially discipline individuals and regularize populations it is apparent that “discourse transmits and produces power” (Foucault, 1978, p.101). Furthermore, as Stuart Hall (1997) argues, individuals are subjected to discourse or “thus become its subjects by subjecting ourselves to its meanings, power and regulation” so that “all discourses, then construct subject-positions” (p.80). Thus, the construction of mental people or so-called non-persons who don’t belong in communities as subjects of knowledge, then, provides a clear definition what philosopher Ian Hacking (2002) calls “making up people.” Consequently, as Hacking argues, the process of naming (only one element in a Foucauldian constitution of subjects) to make people up provides “a particular medico-forensic political language of individual and social control” (p.104) because as subjects of knowledge “who we are is not only what we did, do, and will do but also what we might have done and may do” (p.107). Thus, developmentally disabled teenagers at The Griffin Centre were categorized as potentially dangerous autistic children because of what has been done (there were visits to the centre by the emergency services (Shephard, 2014) and also what they may do, because they are constructed as subjects of knowledge or “made up” as mental non-persons (in a public meeting) who pose an imagined threat to Etobicoke community residents.
Moreover, Charles E. Rosenberg, a historian of medicine, submits that medicalized categorization or diagnosis, which includes the diagnosis of autism, can be tyrannical, especially when it is used “to perform the cultural work of enforcing norms” and define and manage social deviance and subsequently engender “fitting idiosyncratic human beings into constructed and constricting ideal-typical patterns” (Rosenberg, 2002, p.251). The tyranny of diagnosis seemingly enforced on the teenage autistic residents of The Griffin Centre (as social deviants), then, is also compounded by the fact that not only is autism conceived as a problematic social category (in a community meeting) but also that adolescents are often also reified as “a homogenous, problematic and potentially pathological group.” (Ortega and Choudry, 2011, p.329).  Therefore, despite being discursively categorized as mental people or non-people that don’t belong in certain Toronto municipalities the children at The Griffin Centre are also constructed as problematic social subjects according to how both autism and adolescence is sometimes conceived as socially dangerous and then subsequently negotiated as such in knowledge, which, thus, contributes to their discursive construction as humans with less value.  
As Stuart Hall (1997) argues, when detailing the Foucauldian constitution of subjects “discourse produces subjects – figures who personify particular forms of knowledge” (p.80) and if autistic and adolescent figures are personified as problematic individuals, both with the process of naming and the associations of naming, the adolescent and the autistic or the mental or the non-person are subjected to its constructed meanings, (of social deviance) subsequently disciplined (in a public meeting) and regulated accordingly (through categorization).
However, despite the apparent power differentials between a community group, their discriminatory discursive strategies and the subjugated children, who have been individualized as unwanted social deviants, this recent social event also demonstrates, as Foucault argues, that discourse does not transmit a consummate application of power. For discourse can also be “a hindrance, a stumbling block, a point of resistance and a starting point for an opposing strategy,” (Foucault, 1978, p.101) because this social event also generated an indignant mediated response, both to the “spectacle of intolerance” evident at the public meeting and particularly the “inappropriate, deeply offensive and unforgiveable” comments made by Doug Ford (Hume, 2014). In fact Doug Ford was also subsequently singled out in the public domain as a public figure that should have known not to discriminate against autistic teenagers. This affronted process of selection was prompted both by a Scarborough father of an autistic child who suggested the “unbecoming” Ford should “apologize, take sensitivity training and, ultimately, resign” (Armstrong, 2014) and later by a student with Asperger’s syndrome, (which is on the autism disorder spectrum) who questioned Ford on the Mayoral campaign trail to ask why he “reduced people like me to animals and common criminals” and does not explain himself or apologize (Spurr, 2014). Nevertheless, despite Doug Ford’s high profile and problematic involvement in this event and the media's tendency to focus on Ford as the main culprit in an instance of public disability discrimination, when most of the more discriminatory statements were made by Etobicoke community members, a collective mediated response appeared to counter the comments made in the meeting, which could, as Foucault (1978) argues, function to undermine the original discursive strategy, that “exposes it, renders it fragile and makes it possible to thwart it.” (p.101).  The Toronto Star, for example, described the event as “ugly as it was ignorant” (Hume, 2014), former Canadian politician Bob Rae stated that “this is opposite of leadership on mental health” (Jones, 2014) and current Toronto mayor John Tory (then unelected) designated the incident “deeply regrettable and from another age” (Moore, 2014).
In conclusion, what this highly publicized social event demonstrates is that despite community rhetoric that publically disqualifies particular kinds of people and a mediated counter rhetoric that opposes the disqualification, the linguistic elements at play reveal a larger paradigmatic model (of the use of terms, social divisions and oppositional rhetorics) to apprehend ability and disability and conceive of who count as people or what counts as human or even non-human in contemporary Toronto.  Consequently, as Foucault (1978) argues, “we must not imagine a world of discourse divided between accepted discourse and excluded discourse, or between the dominant discourse and the dominated one; but as a multiplicity of discursive elements that come into play in various strategies,” (p.101) because power is exercised at multiple points to also include “a plurality of resistances” (p.96).  According to the Toronto Star this unfortunate incident may have “made Torontonians cringe” (Hume, 2014) but if what counts as human in contemporary Toronto relies on the play of multiple publicized discursive strategies we should constantly pay attention to who is being disciplined and regulated, so-called people and non-people alike, what subject- positions are constructed, why are certain names being used, how are they opposed and for what end, and fundamentally “explain what people are actually doing with language when they speak to each other,” (Billig, 2009, p.162) so that processes of social control and categories of human worth are unveiled, which are seemingly disguised by the illusion that language is transparent. Furthermore, only by unveiling “ugly and ignorant” discursive processes of categorization, like these, for what they are, problematic episodes of discrimination and social control, can they indeed be seen to be “deeply regrettable and from another age,” (Moore, 2014) - hopefully by all.

References

Armstrong, J. (2014, July 3). Complainant says Doug Ford should resign over Griffin Centre comments. Global News. Toronto

Barnes, C. (1992). A Brief History of Discrimination and Disabled People. Disabled People in Britain and Discrimination: A Case for Anti-discrimination Legislation. London. C Hurst & Co.

Billig, M. (2009). Discursive psychology, rhetoric and the issue of agency. Semen, 27. 157-173.

Foucault. M. (1977/1995). Discipline and punish: The birth of the prison. New York: Vintage.

Foucault. M. (1978/1990). The History of sexuality: an introduction, vol. 1. New York. Vintage.

Foucault, M. (1976/2003). Society must be defended: lectures at the Collège de France 1975-1976. Trans. D. Macy. New York: Picador.

Garland- Thomson, R. (1997). Extraordinary bodies: figuring physical disability in American culture and literature. New York. Columbia University Press.

Hacking, I. (2002) Making up people. Historical ontology. Harvard. Harvard University Press.

Hume, C. (2014, May 23). Doug Ford feeds the fear. Toronto Star, Toronto.

Jones, A. (2014, May 18). Doug Ford defends comments about new 'nightmare' youth group home in Toronto. National Post.

Moore, O. (2014, May 18). Community applauds Doug Ford's opposition of youth group home. Globe & Mail.

Ortega, F & Choudhury, S. Wired up differently: autism, adolescence and the politics of neurological identities. Subjectivity, 4 (3). 323-345.

Rosenberg, C. (2002) The tyranny of diagnosis: specific entities and individual experience. The Millbank Quarterly, 80 (2). 237-260.

Shephard, T. (2014, May 16). Etobicoke home for developmentally disabled youth under fire from residents, Councillor Doug Ford. Etobicoke Guardian.

Spurr, B. (2014, October 8). Student with Asperger’s confronts Doug Ford over Autism comments. Now Magazine. Toronto.

Wodak, R. (2004) Critical discourse analysis. Qualitative Research Practice. London: Sage Publications.